Chapter 9. Summary and Conclusion

Having slogged your way through hundreds of pages already, it is only fair that I spare you from a long-drawn-out conclusion. Before the summary, however, I would like to emphasise that despite the content seeming quite in-depth, this book actually barely scratches the surface. There is so much more to say about every topic. Each chapter is best viewed as an appetiser to spur you on to further exploration of these ideas.

Why Critical Thinking Matters

Let’s revisit the core purpose of this text before diving into our final overview. As the title suggests, it aims to equip you with essential critical thinking tools. As the title suggests, it aims to equip you with essential critical thinking tools. But before we summarise the key points, there’s a fundamental question worth revisiting: why does critical thinking matter? Chapters One and Two explored this in depth.

As explored in Chapter One, critical thinking begins with humility. We must acknowledge that our brains weren’t designed as flawless truth-finders. Evolved for survival, they prioritise speed, efficiency, and practical results, with no concern for accuracy. This reliance on shortcuts, while often helpful, can lead to biases and errors. These inherent biases can make us susceptible to flawed logic, distorted thinking, and even strange beliefs. Therefore, the first step towards critical thinking is recognising our brains’ limitations. By acknowledging our biases, we can become more discerning thinkers.

Chapter One also emphasised the pitfalls of navigating the modern information landscape. Through the internet, social media, and news outlets, we have access to an unprecedented amount of information and this constant barrage quickly overwhelms our processing capacity. Companies selling news stories or products use a variety of persuasive techniques to influence our beliefs and behaviour, which can involve emotional appeals, celebrity endorsements, and creating a sense of urgency or scarcity. Even seemingly objective sources operate within ideological perspectives that influence the way they present information.

The relentless focus on turning beliefs into profitable products, often through manipulation, poses a serious threat to critical thinking. Commercial, political, and media interests manufacture and market ideas and facts as products, tailoring manipulative appeals to specific audiences instead of relying on reason and evidence. This relentless pursuit of views and clicks, by both traditional and digital media, fuels sensationalism and biased reporting designed to reinforce predetermined viewpoints. Ultimately, these practices erode informed decision-making, polarise public discourse, and make discerning fact from fiction increasingly difficult within a complex and hostile information landscape.

Despite these challenges, Chapter One offered some positive takeaways: critical thinking is a practical skill that anyone can learn and improve, regardless of their intellectual ability. By understanding how we think, learning new reasoning skills, and practising regularly, we become more discerning thinkers. This benefits us both personally and our societies.

Building Blocks of Critical Thinking

To fully realise the promised benefits, we have to equip ourselves with the right tools. Early in the text, I explained that learning critical thinking is very similar to mastering a new language. In both cases, you have to start with the basic building blocks. In critical thinking, those basics are concepts, which are the foundation for effective thinking. They are the very tools and vocabulary we use to think. Without a strong grasp of these core ideas, our ability to reason effectively is severely hampered. Concepts aren’t just abstract ideas – they’re essential for navigating the world. However, it’s also crucial to recognise that concepts, including propositions, sensations, arguments, and beliefs (all central to this book), are human inventions – imperfect and subject to change. Mastering the concepts in this book will unlock your critical thinking potential. These concepts are the foundation for analysing information, evaluating arguments, and forming sound judgements. They are the key to becoming a critical thinker in the truest sense.

Propositions are the fundamental units of reasoning. They are the tools with which we represent, negotiate, and communicate our understanding of the world. Propositions are unique among statements due to their binary nature: they are either true or false, with no middle ground. They convey facts, assertions, or judgements and can, therefore, be distinguished from interrogative statements (which ask questions) and imperative statements (which give directions or make requests). There are three main types of propositions. Synthetic propositions combine information from the world with language meaning. Analytic propositions are true by definition, relying on logical relationships between words and concepts. Normative propositions express judgements, values, or preferences. Regardless of their type, all propositions require justification. No proposition should be accepted without backing it up with an argument. An argument is a structured sequence of propositions. One proposition serves as the conclusion, representing the main point the argument aims to establish. The remaining propositions, known as premises, function as the justification or evidence supporting the conclusion.

Understanding arguments is central to effective reasoning. The central objective of an argument is to establish the credibility of the conclusion, not necessarily to provide justification for each underlying premise. Providing justification for each premise would require a series of subordinate arguments. In the context of inference (drawing conclusions), premises are often assumed or are considered self-evident. If an underlying proposition is uncertain, the arguer must add supporting arguments to enhance its plausibility.

This book clarified the difference between the types of premises (empirical, rational, and definitional) that are commonly used in arguments. Definitional premises stipulate what is meant by a term. For example, ‘A democracy is a form of government where the people hold power.’ Rational premises focus on reasoning and explaining “why” or “how” things are true, often relying on general principles. For example, ‘All squares have four equal sides.’ Finally, empirical premises appeal to observations as evidence. For example, ‘Penicillin is an antibiotic that kills bacteria.’ A single argument might employ all or none of these specific types of premises.

Reasoning is essentially the process of constructing arguments (combining propositions) and dissecting and evaluating arguments to determine the believability of a concluding proposition, which they aim to corroborate or disprove. The details of arguments might seem far removed from the concerns of everyday life, but almost every claim, belief, or piece of information we encounter can be seen as an implicit argument. So, keep in mind that every news story, ad, or even conversation you have is basically a kind of argument trying to get a point across. For any idea or claim to be taken seriously, it should be presented as a well-structured argument, with clear reasons and evidence backing it up. A superpower of critical thinking is being able to take apart any claim and see how it’s built. You check the reasoning behind it (premises) and see if it holds water and actually supports the main point (conclusion).

Chapter Two embarked on a comprehensive exploration of critical thinking, laying the groundwork for your transformation into a masterful critical thinker. By introducing the fundamental concepts that underpin critical thinking, the initial emphasis on theory laid the groundwork. While the sheer volume of new concepts might have initially felt overwhelming, these concepts are revisited and applied throughout the text. This will have solidified your comprehension and equipped you with the confidence to skilfully apply such concepts in your everyday life.

The Power of Logic and the Pitfalls of Fallacies

Logic, often referred to as the ‘science of reasoning,’ serves as the cornerstone of critical thinking and took centre stage in this theoretical exploration. Here, our focus is on identifying sound arguments. These are arguments with true premises (definitions, reasons, and evidence) that guarantee the truth of the conclusion. For arguments like this, the inferences drawn from the premises to the conclusion are called valid, meaning the connection is truth-preserving. Correctly executed deductive arguments, such as categorical and conditional syllogisms, have the potential to achieve this airtight quality of soundness.

Not all arguments are created equal! Arguments are unsound if either the premises offered are untrue or if the connection between premises and the conclusion is not truth-preserving. In the case of the latter, we are dealing with fallacies, which come in two main varieties. Formal fallacies are the logical equivalent of grammatical errors. They occur when the structure of the argument itself is faulty, regardless of the content of the statements. In the case of formal fallacies, even if the premises are true, the way they’re connected doesn’t guarantee a true conclusion. In contrast, informal fallacies are concerned more with the content and presentation of the argument. They can happen when the reasons used are insufficient, irrelevant, or ambiguous. For example, appealing to emotion instead of logic (fallacy of irrelevancy), or making sweeping generalisations based on limited evidence (fallacy of insufficiency).

While formal fallacies might render an argument technically unsound, it’s important to acknowledge their prevalence in scientific and everyday reasoning. In the case of inductive arguments, which are formally fallacious, conclusions are based on degrees of believability rather than certainty. For instance, inductive tools such as predictive, generalising, analogous, or causal arguments can be powerful tools for understanding the world and form the backbone of scientific explanations. Spotting formal fallacies is like finding cracks in the footpath – important! But sometimes, those “cracked” arguments can still lead us in the right direction, especially in scientific or everyday reasoning. These arguments can be very powerful. For instance, throughout history, an overwhelming number of observations suggested the Sun revolved around the Earth. This inductive argument, while highly convincing based on the accumulated evidence at the time, wasn’t absolutely certain and was eventually proven incorrect by further scientific evidence.

Beyond Logic: Biases and Other Considerations

Our capacity for rational thought is not without other internal challenges. Similar to fallacies, which can lead to flawed arguments, biases drive systematic deviations from rationality. These biases encompass mental shortcuts, known as heuristics, which we employ to process information and make decisions quickly. While these shortcuts can be efficient, they can significantly impact our reasoning in negative ways. By distorting our perceptions and ultimately skewing our judgements, biases lead us to conclusions that are not based on quality reasoning or evidence.

In the face of the ever-expanding body of scientific evidence and its profound impact on our understanding of the world, the ability to critically evaluate such evidence has become an essential skill. Today, countless claims, even those lacking merit, intentionally adopt a veneer of scientific legitimacy. Therefore, a finely honed critical approach towards the quality and quantity of evidence offered for any proposition is invaluable. Appreciating the wide spectrum of quality within scientific evidence – not all studies are equally rigorous or conclusive – is an indispensable starting point. Furthermore, prioritising primary research and subjecting its findings to rigorous scrutiny ensures that propositions are supported by reliable and replicated studies. These analytic skills allow us to critically evaluate scientific evidence, leading to a deeper understanding of how it can be used to establish knowledge.

Building upon the established importance of concepts in developing critical thinking skills, it’s crucial to recognise the equally fundamental role of language itself. Effective reasoning hinges on meticulous attention to language use. Clear and precise communication serves as the bedrock for rational thought, both internally (intrapersonally) and when interacting with others (interpersonally). Scrutinising language use goes beyond simple communication; it impacts the construction of sound and persuasive arguments, as well as the representation and effective transfer of knowledge. While these theoretical foundations might initially appear abstract, they provide the essential framework for translating critical thinking skills into practical real-world applications.

Critical Thinking in Action: Skills to Master

Having established some theoretical foundations, Chapter Two shifted focus towards the practical application of these newly acquired skills. The importance of consistent practice in solidifying your abilities was repeatedly emphasised. This practice encompasses a range of activities, all crucial for developing critical thinking expertise. It equips you to: distinguish between inductive and deductive arguments; identify premise types and how each should be evaluated; construct and deconstruct arguments; identify formal and informal fallacies; untangle language use; and critically evaluate scientific evidence. Through active engagement in these exercises, you’ll hone your skills, leading to a sharper and more effective application of critical thinking in all areas of your life.

Values and Cultivating the Critical Thinking Mindset

Chapter Two acknowledged that critical thinking is not solely a matter of acquiring theoretical knowledge and skills. It also hinges on cultivating the right mindset. We explored the importance of intellectual curiosity, a relentless drive to understand the world around you, and a thirst for new information and new ways of thinking. Open-mindedness is also critical, as it allows you to consider competing perspectives and avoid falling prey to echo-chambers and confirmation bias. A healthy dose of scepticism is also crucial, encouraging you to question claims and assumptions before accepting them. Finally, introspection, the ability to reflect on your own thinking patterns and biases, allows you to identify and address potential shortcomings in your thinking. The text acknowledges that developing these dispositions requires effort but offers significant rewards. These rewards include enhanced clarity of thought, rational decision-making, and a more informed worldview.

Culminating the chapter’s exploration, the text underscored the importance of clarifying your personal values and judgements. These fundamental elements serve as the very foundation upon which your critical thinking journey is built. Whether consciously acknowledged or not, your values and judgements exert a profound influence on the questions you ask, the evidence you seek out, and ultimately, the conclusions you draw. By fostering a deeper understanding of your own values, you empower yourself to approach critical thinking with a heightened sense of self-awareness and objectivity. This, in turn, fosters well-rounded, motivated, and meaningful thinking.

Perception Beyond the Obvious: How Our Brains Build Our Reality

Chapter Three dives into the fascinating world of human perception, challenging the idea that our senses simply show us reality as it is. Instead, it argues that how we see the world is a creative mix of the raw information our senses pick up (bottom-up processes) and how our minds interpret it (top-down processes). Our senses are like picky filters, bombarded with information but only letting a small amount through, and even that gets modified before it reaches the brain. Our thinking isn’t merely a matter of the brain organising and acting on raw sense information either. The brain itself actively transforms and interprets sense information to match what we already know, what we expect to perceive, the language we have to represent things, and our own biases. These ideas contrast with the more common belief that our perceptions accurately and reliably reflect the outside world (an idea called naïve realism). This is clearly illustrated in how we can be fooled by illusions, seeing things that aren’t there or missing things that are right in front of us. The key point is that even with healthy senses, different people see the world in very different ways. The famous “blue dress” example shows this perfectly.

Throughout history, renowned critical thinkers have wrestled with the complexities of human perception. Plato’s allegory of the cave, for instance, famously posited that our view of the external world resembles mere shadows cast on a wall, highlighting the limitations of our senses. Building on this concept, John Locke distinguished between primary qualities, intrinsic properties of objects like size and shape, and secondary qualities, subjective experiences like colour and sound, which arise from our interaction with those objects. Ultimately, Immanuel Kant argued that we can never directly apprehend the “thing-in-itself” (noumena), but only the way it appears to us through our senses (phenomena). These influential thinkers have unmasked the vast gulf that exists between the objective world and our subjective experience of it.

The Active Mind: How Top-Down Processes Shape Our Perception

Our perception of the world is far more intricate than a simple passive recording of external stimuli. It’s closer to an “augmented reality” experience, where top-down processes play a significant role in shaping how we interact with and understand our surroundings. Our existing worldview is a powerful top-down influence, acting as a mental framework that shapes how we interpret new information. This bias toward what we expect is evident in experiments like the anomalous playing cards, which shows how deeply expectations alter perception. This represents a self-perpetuating feedback loop: our beliefs shape our perceptions, which in turn reinforce those same beliefs.  This is just one example of how our minds dynamically construct our experience of reality, with a multitude of ways our internal world interacts with the external environment.

Cognitive biases serve as another compelling illustration of the profound influence top-down processes exert on our perception. Confirmation bias, for example, demonstrates how pre-existing beliefs actively sculpt the information we encounter. This bias compels us to seek out, prioritise, and view with less scrutiny information that aligns with our existing views. Conversely, it makes us less likely to retain or even notice evidence that contradicts those beliefs. This creates another self-reinforcing cycle: our initial assumptions influence the type of information we are exposed to, ultimately solidifying those same beliefs. Confirmation bias, along with other top-down processes, contributes to the remarkable resilience of our existing beliefs, making them resistant to revision, even in the face of readily available contradictory evidence.

Mitigating Bias: Cultivating a More Balanced View

The first step towards mitigating the distorting effects of top-down influences on our perception is acknowledging these inherent limitations. This necessitates cultivating intellectual humility and taking an active role in counteracting these biases. Firstly, such modesty compels us to recognise the ever-present possibility of error in our current perceptions, understandings, and beliefs. Secondly, intellectual courage is required to actively seek out evidence that contradicts our existing beliefs, no matter how strongly we hold them. Open-mindedness further fosters this process by keeping us receptive to new information that could reshape our perspectives. Finally, emotional detachment from our current views allows for objective evaluation of incoming data, free from the clinging bias of emotional attachment. Through this commitment to intellectual humility, we strive to pierce the veil of our own biases and achieve a more accurate and balanced understanding of the world. One key strategy involves prioritising the falsification of beliefs and assumptions. While confirming evidence is readily available and easily found, it holds little value. The true power of evidence lies in actively seeking evidence that falsifies our beliefs, a process that vastly improves our understanding of the world.

The Tricky Business of Knowledge

Chapter Four attempts to tackle concerns involving the concept of knowledge, particularly how we substantiate our claims to possessing it. The discussion begins by acknowledging Plato’s tripartite definition of knowledge as “justified true belief,” which establishes three essential criteria: belief, justification, and truth. While seemingly straightforward, fulfilling these criteria proves to be far more difficult than one might initially anticipate. Both belief and knowledge involve a mental state of holding something to be true. We can believe things for various reasons, from personal experience to societal norms, while knowledge requires justification for that belief. Therefore, our theories of knowledge must find a way to distinguish between mere belief and genuine knowledge.

The challenge of distinguishing mere belief from knowledge underscores the much-emphasised importance of structuring knowledge claims as arguments. At its core, a knowledge claim is a proposition, a statement about the world, that relies on other propositions, known as premises, to provide justification (a very familiar formula to you by now). An unsupported assumption arises when a proposition is presented without any supporting evidence or reasoning. These unsupported assumptions can be deceptive, even if the proposition itself happens to be true. The very absence of justification renders the truth value (its status as true or not) unknowable, as we lack a credible basis for accepting the claim. The explicit formulation of knowledge claims as arguments allows us to identify and address unsupported assumptions, thereby ensuring that our beliefs rest on a defensible foundation.

Building a Strong Case

The methods for justifying knowledge claims depend on the nature of the claim itself. To this end, we introduce a significant and highly influential distinction developed by the philosopher David Hume: Hume’s Fork. This concept serves as a crucial tool for differentiating between two fundamental categories of knowledge claims: analytic and synthetic. Analytic propositions, which deal with the logic of language itself, can often be proven with certainty by just analysing the definitions and how the words relate to each other. It’s like unpacking the built-in meaning of the concepts. Analytic propositions offer a clearer path to justification, potentially achieving the certainty Plato envisioned. For example, justifying “all bachelors are unmarried” relies solely on understanding the terms “bachelor” and “unmarried.” Synthetic propositions, on the other hand, deal with facts about the real world. Here, we need evidence – stuff we can observe, experiment with, or reports of others’ observations and experiments – to justify the claim. With evidence, synthetic claims become more believable, but it’s not quite the same as the rock-solid certainty you get with analytic propositions. Since synthetic knowledge is about the real world, there’s always a chance new evidence might pop up and change things. In simpler terms, while we can strengthen the believability of synthetic claims with evidence, they can never attain the same level of guaranteed truth as analytic propositions.

At best, synthetic propositions can only ever be elevated to the status of “facts” when compelling evidence supports them. A fact represents something we hold to be true with a high degree of confidence, stemming from a strong foundation of evidence. This justification process distinguishes facts from hypotheses or conjectures, which are essentially propositions awaiting rigorous testing and evidence accumulation. Hypotheses, essentially propositions awaiting the crucible of testing, function as educated guesses informed by theoretical frameworks. If substantiated through rigorous testing, these hypotheses become prime candidates for eventual elevation to the status of fact, though never attaining absolute immutability.

Deductive vs. Inductive Reasoning: A Balancing Act

This focus on justification is relevant to understanding an important distinction between deductive and inductive reasoning. The justification of knowledge claims isn’t all or nothing – it’s more like a spectrum of varying confidence between unlikelihood and certainty. Sound deductive reasoning provides certainty, while inductive reasoning offers varying degrees of believability or plausibility. Analytic propositions can be justified through deductive reasoning applied to definitions and established relationships between terms. This approach crucially delivers the highly sought-after certainty that Plato strived for. Conversely, dealing with matters of fact in the external world, synthetic propositions necessitate inductive reasoning that appeals to evidence gathered through observation or experimentation. This empirical approach strengthens the believability of the claim, but inherently differs from the absolute certainty that’s achievable when deductive reasoning is employed for analytic propositions.

While deductive reasoning provides a high degree of certainty for analytic propositions, it comes with a key limitation. These arguments, often focused on analysing definitions and established relationships within language, are considered “explicative.” This means they primarily clarify existing knowledge by unpacking the inherent meaning of the concepts involved. In essence, they don’t venture beyond what is already implied within the starting premises. Conversely, inductive arguments, though offering less certainty, possess the advantage of being “ampliative.” By incorporating evidence from the real world and drawing conclusions based on observations or experiments, they actively expand our knowledge. This trade-off between certainty and the generation of new knowledge underscores the importance of understanding the role of both deductive and inductive reasoning in the pursuit of knowledge.

From Theory to Evidence: A Dance Between Deduction and Induction

Inductive and deductive reasoning are cornerstones of the scientific method. Deductive reasoning takes the lead in formulating testable hypotheses by applying modus ponens (if P, then Q). For example, the theory that adding baking soda to vinegar creates a fizzy reaction (P) can be used deductively to generate a hypothesis (Q). This hypothesis might state that a sample of vinegar will fizz if I add baking soda to it. The study’s outcome dictates the next step. If the data contradicts the hypothesis (i.e., we observe not Q or no fizz), the use of modus tollens allows us to reject the original theory (i.e., we infer not P). Conversely, if the study confirms the hypothesis (i.e., we observe Q), we must then rely on inductive reasoning to link this confirming evidence to the synthetic claim. This is because confirming data (Q) doesn’t guarantee the truth of the initial theory (P). That is, we cannot validly reason from supporting data (i.e., confirming Q observation) to the truth of the theoretical claim (therefore, P) or we will commit the formal fallacy known as affirming the consequent (the vinegar might be fizzing because I shook it). To avoid this, scientists reformulate the argument, so that the confirmed hypothesis becomes a new premise in an inductive argument, which offers stronger support for the original theoretical claim. For these reasons, confirming evidence for a hypothesis is weak because, as we know, a true conclusion doesn’t guarantee true premises.

In this way, understanding the foundations of knowledge, particularly scientific knowledge, necessitates a rigorous examination of justification. Though the quest to justify knowledge of the external world may seem beyond reach at times, the power knowledge grants us fuels our unwavering pursuit. As Francis Bacon aptly observed, “knowledge itself is power.” Indeed, it is not mere belief but genuine, well-supported knowledge that empowers us to influence the world around us, shaping it in accordance with our values. By critically evaluating the justification for our knowledge claims, we ensure the reliability and utility of our knowledge. This, in turn, allows us to make informed decisions and enact meaningful change, fostering a world shaped by accurate understanding rather than blind belief.

Language: The Bedrock of Knowledge

Knowledge, as Bacon noted, empowers us, but only when justified. Since language forms the very foundation of our knowledge and lies at the heart of justification, understanding knowledge demands a dual exploration: its methods and the role of language. Wittgenstein’s insights shed light on this interplay. He emphasised the profound influence language exerts on our perception and understanding of reality. His famous statement, “the limits of my language mean the limits of my world,” underscored how language defines the boundaries of what we can think and express. Indeed, language serves as the primary vehicle for our thoughts, beliefs, and communication. If the limits of language truly define the boundaries of our world, wouldn’t understanding both language and its limitations be crucial for uncovering the limits of our knowledge and our understanding of reality?

Understanding Language, Understanding Reality

Language is a complex and rule-governed system composed of arbitrary symbols. Devoid of inherent meaning, these symbols derive their significance from their relationships with other symbols within the broader linguistic network, and it is only through social consensus that they come to represent specific concepts, objects, and experiences – both internally and within the external world. Thus, meaning arises holistically, emerging from the intricate web of connections and interactions within the language system as a whole.

The ability to represent ideas and concrete objects symbolically underpins two key achievements of human cognitive evolution: thought and communication. Symbolic representation offers us tremendous flexibility and utility. We can manipulate, contemplate, and share ideas far more easily than concrete objects, greatly enhancing our problem-solving and cooperative abilities. However, the power of abstraction comes with a trade-off. Symbolic representations of reality are always inherently disconnected from the concrete world.

This power of abstraction, which is fundamental to human thought and communication, is embodied in our use of language. Importantly, by releasing our thinking from the confines of dealing only with the concrete, abstraction also allows us to grapple with concepts that defy direct experience, such as infinity, justice, or the nature of consciousness.

Several key points emerged from our definition of language. First, language holds meaning only within a shared social context. Second, the meanings attached to symbols are socially constructed and subjective. This subjectivity, along with the ever-evolving nature of language use, explains why dictionaries must continually update their definitions.

A counterintuitive feature of language is its internal self-referentiality. The meaning of a symbol doesn’t come from the real-world thing it might represent. Instead, meaning emerges from the ever-shifting web of relationships between symbols within a language. For example, the word “tree” doesn’t represent the concept of a tree because it has any resemblance to one. Its meaning comes from how it relates to other words within our language system. Furthermore, meaning frequently emerges from the context of entire sentences (syntactic meaning) rather than individual words (semantic meaning), and from how those words are used (pragmatic meaning).

The Language-Thought-Belief Nexus

The extent to which language shapes our thoughts and experiences is a fascinating and hotly debated topic. The Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, also known as linguistic determinism, posits that language strongly dictates our perceptions. This contrasts slightly with Wittgenstein’s perspective, which saw language as setting boundaries around how we comprehend and express our experiences. In addition to the other top-down processes discussed in Chapter Three, language also influences our perception in a multitude of ways, shaping what we notice, what we give importance to, and the beliefs we subsequently form.

This discussion highlights the deep connection between ideas, beliefs, and language. Ideas and beliefs themselves are built out of words, and their meanings depend on how these words relate within the broader language system. One practical consequence of this is that we can only have ideas or hold beliefs about concepts that we can express symbolically. This also sheds light on why it’s so difficult to abandon outdated beliefs, a challenge we explored in Chapter Three. Their linguistic nature makes them feel like an essential part of who we are and how we make sense of the world, so letting them go can be deeply destabilising.

Language in Science and Psychology

Not only does the profound connection between language and belief shape our personal understanding of the world, but it also fundamentally reshapes our collective understanding, a point that is exemplified by scientific revolutions. As Thomas Kuhn argued, these revolutions are less about new discoveries and more about a fundamental shift in the language we use to describe the world. These transformations are intrinsically linked to our use of frameworks for understanding the world. As scientific knowledge changes over time, the concepts and terminology used to define and explain reality must also change. New theories often require the creation of new concepts, change the meanings of existing ones, or completely redefine the relationships between established terms. Consequently, scientific revolutions necessitate a profound reshaping of our conceptual frameworks and the linguistic tools used to express those concepts. Failing to appreciate the repercussions of language change in scientific revolutions carries the risk of misunderstanding the nature of scientific theories and the concepts they employ.

Similar to scientific theories, psychological constructs can be susceptible to misunderstanding if we fail to appreciate the decisive role of language in their creation, use, and revision. These abstract concepts (e.g., “intelligence” or “personality”), which are crucial for understanding human behaviour and mental processes, are often mistaken for fixed realities. It’s important to remember that terms like “mental illness” are human-made tools we use to categorise observable phenomena. They are not real entities in themselves. Reification, which is the tendency to treat abstract concepts as tangible things, is fraught with danger, since it leads to overly simplistic and inflexible thought patterns, thereby hindering our understanding and perception of the world.

When we forget that concepts are disposable tools shaped by history and culture, we become less receptive to new evidence or alternative frameworks that challenge our assumptions. This hinders progress in understanding the extraordinary complexity of human behaviour and mental processes.

The Persuasive Power of Language

Finally, we explored the power of language as a rhetorical tool for persuasion. Because of its ability to shape thoughts, emotions, and perceptions, language holds immense persuasive potential. Two common rhetorical devices are emotive language and colloquialisms. Emotive language strategically employs words and phrases with strong emotional associations (e.g., “patriotic,” “devastating,” “inspiring”) to elicit desired responses in an audience, whereas colloquialisms, informal expressions characteristic of everyday speech (e.g., “take it easy,” “get the picture,”), can enhance the relatability of a message and foster a sense of connection between the speaker and the audience. However, like dialectical idioms, colloquialisms can also be exclusionary (though sometimes unintentionally), limiting understanding within specific communities.

Understanding how language functions, both in shaping our internal thoughts and our communication with others, is fundamental to critical thinking. This knowledge empowers us to critically evaluate information, recognising the power of language to persuade, but also its potential to mislead. Furthermore, when analysing arguments, we must be mindful of how linguistic choices can subtly influence our assessment of the truthfulness of their propositions and the validity of their inferences.

Language, Logic, and Critical Evaluation

Let’s delve into a specific example by examining one of the most famous types of deductive arguments: categorical syllogisms. These arguments focus on categories of things and their properties or memberships. The building blocks of categorical syllogisms are categorical propositions, which come in four types: universal affirmative (A), universal negative (E), particular affirmative (I), and particular negative (O). These types vary according to both their quantity (referring to all or only some members of a category) and quality (affirming or denying a characteristic). Analysing the quantity and quality of propositions helps us determine how properties are claimed to be distributed within and across the categories or terms. Recall that the word ‘term’ is simply a technical way to refer to the categories of things a proposition discusses.

Most propositions involve two key terms: the subject (what’s being discussed) and the predicate (the characteristic applied to the subject). In the statement “All whales are mammals,” “whales” is the subject and “mammals” is the predicate. Distribution refers to whether a proposition talks about all members of a category. Here, “whales” (the subject) is distributed (referring to all whales), while “mammals” (the predicate) is undistributed (not all mammals). This structure makes the statement a universal affirmative (A-type) proposition. Understanding distribution is crucial for evaluating categorical syllogisms, as specific rules govern how distributed terms affect a syllogism’s validity.

Dissecting categorical syllogisms involves a step-by-step analysis of its key elements. First, we examine the constituent propositions, which are the individual statements that make up the syllogism. We analyse their type to determine whether they are universal affirmative, universal negative, particular affirmative, or particular negative. Next, we look at the distribution of terms, identifying whether a proposition talks about all members of a category (distributed term) or only some members (undistributed term). We then identify three key term roles: the major term (often the predicate of the conclusion), the minor term (often the subject of the conclusion), and the middle term (appears in both premises but never in the conclusion). A valid syllogism must adhere to six specific rules governing the number of terms allowed, the required distribution of the middle term, and restrictions on negative premises and conclusions. Understanding these elements and their governing rules allows us to systematically analyse categorical syllogisms, separating those with valid, sound reasoning from fallacious arguments with faulty structures.

Conditional arguments form another prevalent type of deductive reasoning. They utilise two fundamental principles, modus ponens and modus tollens, which we saw at work in the vinegar and baking soda experiment. Both principles are grounded in a fundamental conditional premise, structured as ‘If P, then Q,’ where P represents the antecedent and Q the consequent. In modus ponens, the second premise affirms the antecedent (P), leading to a valid conclusion affirming the consequent (Q). For example: If you have the pin-code (P), then you can access my phone (Q). Since you have the pin-code (P), you can access my phone (Q). Modus tollens, conversely, denies the consequent in its second premise, leading to validly denying the antecedent in the conclusion. For example: If you have the pin-code (P), then you can access my phone (Q). You couldn’t access my phone (not Q); therefore, you don’t have the pin-code (not P).

Common errors in applying modus ponens and modus tollens can lead to invalid inferences, just as with any form of argument. ‘Affirming the consequent’ (fallacious modus ponens) and ‘denying the antecedent’ (fallacious modus tollens) are formal logical fallacies that lead to invalid inferences. Understanding these common fallacies is crucial for avoiding faulty reasoning. It is as applicable in everyday life as it is in the process of scientific inquiry.

Induction and Scientific Reasoning

Scientific knowledge doesn’t solely depend on deductive reasoning, which, when valid, is truth-preserving since it guarantees a true conclusion from true premises. It also relies heavily on inductive arguments, particularly in the context of using observational evidence to support hypotheses. While inductive arguments can lend substantial support to a theory, their inherent limitations must be acknowledged. They do not provide absolute certainty, as they are not truth-preserving in the way deductive arguments are. Therefore, conclusions drawn from inductive reasoning are not guaranteed to be true, making them provisional. There’s always the possibility of a future observation that contradicts the established conclusion. For example, countless observations might support the claim “all swans are white.” However, the discovery of a single black swan would throw the entire generalisation into question.

We examined several types of induction, including enumerative induction. This approach uses repeated observations of a pattern to make predictions or generalisations. For example, countless tasty meals might lead to the conclusion, “all bread is delicious.” However, as we know, no matter how many supporting observations we make, this generalisation can be overturned by a single stale sandwich. Another method of inductive reasoning is analogical reasoning, where scientists draw conclusions based on similarities between two things. They might compare the structure and function of a newly discovered organ to a known organ in another species to infer its potential function.

Causal inference is the process of identifying cause-and-effect relationships. While it’s a highly sought-after goal in science, since understanding causation allows us to control and predict phenomena, it’s also one of the most challenging tasks. To support a convincing causal hypothesis, scientists need to meet three key conditions. First, there must be a consistent relationship between the potential cause and the observed effect (correlation). For instance, increased exposure to sunlight might be correlated with higher rates of skin cancer. Second, the cause must precede the effect (time sequence). For example, sun exposure has to occur before skin cancer develops. Finally, scientists must carefully consider and attempt to eliminate alternative explanations for this effect. Are there other reasons, besides sunlight, that could contribute to the development of skin cancer?

In both inductive and deductive reasoning, an argument’s strength rests on the soundness of its premises or reasons, regardless of whether they are definitional, rational, or empirical. In Chapter Seven, we’ll delve into the ways reasons can be flawed or fallacious. Recognising these fallacies is crucial for overcoming faulty arguments.

Reasoning Content vs. Structure

An important distinction must first be made between the content and structure of arguments. Content refers to the subject matter – what the argument discusses. Structure pertains to how premises and conclusions are arranged, influencing the argument’s logical form. While Chapter Six emphasised structural issues within arguments, Chapter Seven focused on weaknesses related to content, specifically the meaning of what the reasons express. These content-related weaknesses are known as informal fallacies. Remember, formal fallacies involve errors in the argument’s structure without regard for the content’s truth or relevance.

Varieties of Fallacious Reasoning

When delving into the reasons why arguments fail to stand as convincing, it’s essential to understand the key issues that undermine their effectiveness. A primary concern is when arguments are built on insufficient reasons, which means they lack the necessary information or strength in their premises to convincingly support their conclusions. This shortfall is often evident with faulty generalisations, where the evidence is too thin to back broad conclusions, or weak causal inferences, where the link between cause and effect is tenuously established. Similarly, arguments can falter when based on unconvincing analogies, drawing comparisons with insufficient similarities, or when they rely on unjustified expectations, predicting futures without enough evidence. While these gaps can sometimes be bridged by adding more detailed premises, the underlying issue of insufficiency remains a significant hurdle.

Another stumbling block for arguments is the reliance on irrelevant reasons. These are premises that, despite their presence, have no real connection to the claim being made. They can take various forms, such as ad hominem attacks, which sidestep the actual argument to critique the person making it, or red herrings, which introduce distractions to divert the discussion. Straw man fallacies also fall into this category, where an opponent’s position is misrepresented to make it easier to attack, alongside appeals to emotion, which forgo logical reasoning in favour of emotional influence.

Ambiguity in reasoning represents a third group of informal fallacies. This can manifest at different levels, from the word level, where a single term may carry multiple meanings, leading to equivocation, to the sentence level, where grammatical ambiguities can muddle the intended message. Additionally, composition and division fallacies can erroneously ascribe characteristics of the parts to the whole or vice versa, and shifting the goalposts can alter the criteria for what’s deemed sufficient evidence, both of which obscure clear reasoning.

Cognitive Biases: The Hidden Filters

Informal fallacies and cognitive biases are intricately linked. Our susceptibility to fallacious arguments often originates from cognitive biases—those innate mental tendencies that subtly, yet profoundly, influence our thinking, often without our awareness. Picture your perception as being filtered through coloured lenses, so subtly integrated that you might not even realise their presence. These lenses symbolise the various cognitive biases that shape how we interpret the world. For instance, an optimism bias might cast a rosy hue on everything, highlighting the positive, while minimising perceived risks. Recognising these biases is akin to becoming aware of the lenses themselves, enabling you to see the world more clearly and adjust your perspective for a more balanced view.

To illustrate the nature and impact of cognitive biases on our thinking, let’s recap some common examples. We have already touched on confirmation bias in this chapter, which describes our tendency to favour information that confirms our existing beliefs. Overcoming confirmation bias requires active effort to ensure we are considering multiple sides of an issue and to seek out falsifying evidence rather than succumbing to the irresistible pull of corroborative evidence.

Another common bias is self-serving bias. This bias manifests in our tendency to attribute our successes to internal factors like our own skill or effort, while attributing failures to external factors beyond our control. This bias serves to protect our self-esteem but can hinder our ability to learn from mistakes, accurately credit others’ strengths, and grow as individuals.

The backfire effect presents another interesting wrinkle in our ability to reason. This phenomenon describes the ironic situation where people presented with evidence that contradicts their existing beliefs often become even more entrenched in those beliefs. Instead of reevaluating their stance, they may dismiss the evidence or even see it as a personal attack, further solidifying their initial position.

In-group bias highlights the powerful influence of social categorisation on our thinking. This bias leads us to favour members of groups we identify with, while potentially viewing out-groups with suspicion or distrust. In-group bias can manifest in a variety of ways, from cheering for our favourite sports team to favouring job candidates from similar backgrounds. While in-group bias can have positive social implications like fostering group cohesion, it can also lead to prejudice and discrimination if left unchecked.

By understanding the interplay between informal fallacies and cognitive biases, we can become more aware of the potential pitfalls in our own reasoning and develop the critical thinking skills necessary to evaluate arguments effectively. This course aims to sharpen your ability to detect flawed reasoning. While lists of fallacies and biases are helpful learning tools, the goal is to instinctively recognise when reasons are insufficient, irrelevant, or ambiguous – with or without specific labels. With practice, you’ll gain fluency in identifying and dismantling faulty reasoning.

Normative Propositions: A New Challenge

Chapter 8 introduced a new challenge: we move from propositions primarily concerned with establishing truth values (such as the analytic and synthetic propositions, covered in depth earlier in this chapter) to the realm of normative propositions. In contrast to analytic propositions, which dissect the inherent meaning of terms, and synthetic propositions, which rely on empirical observation, normative propositions assert value judgements, expressing ideals and prescriptions regarding how the world ought to be. This focus on desired states rather than factual description renders the justification of normative propositions a uniquely challenging endeavour.

Hume’s Guillotine: Separating ‘Is’ from ‘Ought’

Unsurprisingly, methodologies that establish truths of analytic and synthetic propositions are insufficient for normative claims. Specifically, determining ethical rightness or wrongness bears little resemblance to linguistic analysis (as with analytic propositions) or the verification of observable facts (as with synthetic propositions). Yet, a common error, one David Hume explicitly warned against in his ‘is-ought’ distinction (often nicknamed “the guillotine” for its abrupt cutting off of illogical leaps), is the conflation of the descriptive and the normative. Hume’s argument contends that no amount of rational deduction can transform purely factual statements into prescriptions for moral action. For example, the statement “all swans observed so far are white” (descriptive) does not logically justify the claim “all swans should be white” (normative). Critical evaluation of such claims necessitates a keen eye for unstated assumptions, which bridge the gap between factual observations and moral prescriptions.

Exploring Ethical Theories

Chapter 8 delved into influential ethical theories, seeking frameworks to guide our critical assessment of normative propositions. Virtue ethics, with its origins in the philosophies of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, emphasises the cultivation of admirable character traits as foundational to ethical behaviour. Within this framework, we evaluate the moral worth of a normative proposition based on the virtues it reflects. For example, a proposition advocating generosity in times of need embodies the virtue of compassion. In contrast, deontological ethics, championed by Immanuel Kant, posits a system of universal moral laws derived through rigorous reason. Under deontology, our primary duty is unwavering adherence to those laws, irrespective of context and potential consequences. Consider a Kantian perspective on lying: even if a lie might prevent harm, it violates the universal law of truth-telling and is, therefore, deemed morally wrong. Consequentialist theories, most notably the utilitarianism of John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham, evaluate normative propositions entirely on their outcomes. These theories advocate for actions and decisions that maximise overall happiness or well-being. For instance, from a utilitarian perspective, redistributing wealth to reduce extreme poverty would be considered morally justified if it ultimately produces a net increase in well-being for broader social groups.

Advantages and Limitations of Ethical Frameworks

As with any philosophical theory, each ethical framework presents a complex landscape of both advantages and limitations. Virtue ethics offers a multi-faceted and adaptable approach to normative propositions, encouraging the development of a moral compass aligned with deeply held values. For example, confronted with a situation where sharing confidential information could prevent harm, virtue ethics would guide us to weigh virtues like honesty and compassion against each other. However, this framework leaves us with the complex challenge of determining which character traits are universally virtuous and opens a perilous loophole: actions considered morally abhorrent by most could potentially be justified if they align with a corrupt or deeply misguided set of values.

Deontological ethics provides the compelling appeal of clarity and consistency by asserting the existence of universal moral laws. Consider the act of stealing: in a deontological framework, it remains ethically wrong, regardless of circumstances or consequences, as it violates the inherent law against taking another’s property. Yet, a fundamental question arises: what is the ultimate source of these laws, and how are they justified? While Kant introduces the categorical imperative as a means of providing this justification, its applicability and persuasiveness are not universally accepted.

Consequentialism initially appears to offer a pragmatic solution by focusing solely on the results of actions. From this perspective, a decision that produces the greatest overall happiness or well-being would be deemed morally desirable, even if achieving it requires what might otherwise be considered ethically questionable means. However, this theory leaves us with an almost insurmountable task: how can we reliably predict and weigh the totality of positive and negative consequences, both immediate and far-reaching, for any given action?

Despite their inherent flaws, these ethical frameworks serve as invaluable instruments for tackling the complex challenge of justifying normative propositions. Realistically, our everyday decision-making about morality likely incorporates elements from all these approaches, with varying emphasis depending on the specific context and intended outcome. As with many facets of critical thinking, self-awareness and flexibility of thought are essential when evaluating the value judgements ingrained within normative propositions.

Beyond the Book: Critical Thinking in Action

Throughout our exploration of topics in critical thinking, such as logic, perception, knowledge, morality, and the fascinating ways language shapes our thoughts, we’ve navigated many intricate ideas and uncovered how they shape the way we think, interact, and see the world. These chapters have built a solid foundation for embarking on a lifelong path to master critical thinking and highlighted the countless ways it can deepen our understanding and broaden our perspectives. Now, it’s clear that critical thinking isn’t just a theoretical exercise. Rather, it’s an essential skill that requires ongoing training in order to successfully navigate the complexities of our modern world.

As Socrates famously asserted, “the unexamined life is not worth living.” Building on this profound insight, I likewise believe that the unexamined belief is not worth having. Critical thinking embodies this principle. It goes beyond spotting arguments or picking out fallacies. It’s an approach to understanding that values clarity, accuracy, and open-mindedness. It asks us to examine not only the information we encounter but also our interactions with that information and our role in the social practices that mould our collective understanding.

By embracing critical thinking, we don’t just learn to separate truth from falsehood; we gain the ability to engage with the world more thoughtfully, responsibly, and compassionately. This book is not the end of the journey, but a starting point – a springboard for continued learning, questioning, and growth. As you move forward, equipped with these conceptual tools, I hope you discover both answers to your questions and the wisdom to question those very answers. The journey of critical thinking never ends, and with every step, you’ll gain a more enlightened understanding of the rich complexities of human knowledge and experience.

Licence

Icon for the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International License

MASTERING THINKING Copyright © 2024 by University of Southern Queensland is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book